GRACE MINISTRY MYANMAR

John 13:34 “A new command I give you: Love one another. As I have loved you, so you must love one another."

Wednesday, November 23, 2016

Protestant Theology in Germany


Protestant Theology in Germany

By Michael Moxter and Ingolf U. Dalferth

Protestant theology in Germany originated with the Reformers of the sixteenth century. Of diverse intellectual and theological origins, it was from the beginning an academic discipline taught at the universities of the Protestant states of Germany. The rich variety and often contro­versial pluralism which it developed in the course of its history had theological, but also political, origins. It derived from the state-based reorganization of church life and public educa­tion according to the principle cuius regio, eius religio whose impact on the complex develop­ment of Protestant theology in Germany can hardly be overestimated.

Typically, Protestant theology is predomi­nantly soteriological in orientation. It reflects a Christ-centred Trinitarian faith in God (solus Christus) and hence accepts the Word of God as testified by Scripture as the supreme arbiter in all matters of faith (sola scriptura). Its formative period was the seventeenth century, when Lutheran and Reformed divines worked out their doctrinal systems of scholastic orthodoxy in response to post-Tridentine Roman Catholi-[490]cism and in confessional and political opposition to each other. It moved into its self-reflective phase in the eighteenth century when the internal criticism of pietism and the external rise of enlightened reason forced it to define its distinctly Protestant (as opposed to merely confessional Lutheran or Calvinist) position beyond its rejection of the Roman papacy and its claims to authority in more positive theological terms. Philosophically generalized by German idealism, its ethos had a formative impact on the intellectual and cultural formation of German society in the nineteenth century. It suffered a major setback through the disestablishment of the Protestant churches after 1918 and the collaboration of many Protestants with the Nazi regime, from which it never wholly recovered. It still holds a privileged position by being taught at state universities by state-paid professors of theology. But although it has produced many fine theologians and important contributions to the study of theology in this century, its influence on society at large and on church life in particular has been continuously diminishing.

The term 'Protestant'

Originally the term 'Protestant' referred to the legal protest made by six princes and fourteen south German cities at the Diet of Speyer in 1529. This protest was directed not against Rome but against the rescinding of the unanimous declaration of the earlier Diet of Speyer in 1526 that until a General Council met every prince should be free to introduce religious changes. The religious import of this legal protestation was that in questions of religion and faith the only authority to be obeyed was the Word of God, not a political body or a majority vote. It was in the light of this that Lutherans, and soon all Reformation movements opposed to Rome, were called 'Protestant' by their critics, while they them­selves preferred to describe their position as 'evangelical'. But the separation from the more radical enthusiast and Anabaptist movements after 1525, the breach between Martin Luther and Ulrich Zwingli in 1529 and the Peace of Augsburg in 1555 made it quite clear that mainstream 'evangelical' Protestantism re­mained firmly in the traditions of western Christianity and that the opposition between Lutherans and Calvinists was as great as their common opposition to Rome. It was not before the seventeenth century and the bitter experi­ences of the wars of religion that both Lutherans and Calvinists adopted – via England and western Europe – the neutral (political) de­scription of Protestants as their common name. By this time it was clear that the Protestant break with Rome was permanent; that the religious unity of the empire could not be restored by force; that western Christianity was definitely dissolved into a variety of confessional traditions, churches and religious movements; and that this plurality of conflicting religious convictions could only coexist peace­fully if the common affairs of human life were based on natural law and principles of reason­ableness established independently of religious commitments. So the eighteenth century saw European culture well on the way from a pluri-religious to an increasingly secular society.

Protestant self-understanding

For Protestant theology to come to grips with this, it had to work out its self-understanding in changing contexts and with differing emphases. While there is a clear continuity of theological orientation due to the confessional self-determi­nation of the Lutheran and Reformed churches in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, German Protestant theology has produced different types of theology in different periods since the Reformation. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries it defined itself primarily vis-à-vis Roman Catholicism and the more radical spiritualist and (Ana)Baptist traditions in Lutheran or Reformed (Calvinist) terms. The rejection of obedience to the Roman papacy (Bossuet, [1688] 1841), the self-demarcation against Baptist, spiritualist and anti-Trinitarian movements, and the opposition between Lutheran and Calvinist orientations have since been fundamental traits of Protestant theology.

In the eighteenth century the primary points of reference were the dissenting and noncon­formist pietist traditions, the enlightened synthesis of humanist and Renaissance tradi­tions with the new spirit of empirical and mathematical science, rational philosophy and Confucian ethics, and the growing enlightenment secularism. This led to an even greater internal diversification of Protestant theology [491] and to the disintegration of confessional orthodoxy by rationalism and supranaturalism, neologism and a growing historical conscious­ness. The self-conscious engagement with rationalist and idealist philosophies and the wholehearted commitment to critical historical scholarship have left their mark on German Protestant theology.

In the nineteenth century it had to come to grips with the rise of nationalism, industrialism and the social problems in its wake, but also with the progress of the natural sciences, technology and historical scholarship. This led, on the one hand, to the resurgence of a confessionalism based on the national churches, with a strong commitment to missionary, charitable and social activities. On the other it also prompted unionist attempts to overcome the old Protestant antagonisms and paved the way to neo-Protestant liberalism, preoccupation with the historical sciences, identification with the culture and religious system of the day, and the loss of eschatological outlook. Protestant social ethics, which had always been torn between honouring the authorities in power as ordained of God (especially in the Lutheran traditions) and prophetically denouncing the world in the light of the reign of Christ and the coming kingdom of God (in the more Calvinist traditions), now became closely wedded to the bourgeois values of national German society.

The twentieth century not only saw the disestablishment of the Protestant churches after 1918, the collapse of Protestant liberalism and conservative confessionalism before and during the Nazi regime, and the failure of many churches and individuals to resist the lure of nationalism and to find their place in a democratic society. It was also characterized by the rediscovery of an eschatological orienta­tion, the opposition of dialectical theology to religious liberalism, conservative traditionalism and pietist subjectivism, the experiences of church struggle, Holocaust and the political disasters of the Second World War, the rise of religious pluralism and indifferentism, the ecumenical movement and the overcoming of the old divide between Lutheran and Reformed churches, and the economic, social and political developments that led to European unity and the collapse of the Marxist regimes in eastern Europe towards the end of the century. Protestant theology in this period became more international and ecumenical in outlook and less prone to confessional demarcations against other Christian churches both within and outside the Protestant camp. It became hermeneutically sensitive to the difference between the Word of God and the Bible, opposed to Enlight­enment theism and its metaphysical conse­quences, and increasingly Trinitarian in orientation. But it also became aware of the haunting legacy of Christian anti-Judaism, the depreciation of women in the church, the issues of theological feminism, and the need to develop new forms of political theology. It grappled with the manifold moral and social problems of a secular industrial society, its materialism and religious indifferentism, the erosion of commit­ment to the Christian churches and their progressive marginalization in German society. So in the latter part of the century German Protestant theology was more open to theologi­cal developments outside the German-speaking world than at any time since the sixteenth century.

Central problems of Protestant thought

It follows from what has been said that the central problems of German Protestant theology were characteristically different at different times in its history. In the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries its major tasks were to clarify the stand of evangelical Protestantism vis-à-vis both Roman Catholicism and radical ('enthusiast') religious movements such as the Anabaptists and anti-Trinitarians, and to sort out the doctrinal differences between Lutheran and Calvinist convictions within the Protestant camp. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the emphasis shifted to the internal differences between theological orthodoxy and pietism and to the external differences between, on the one hand, the claims of revealed religion and, on the other, Enlightenment rationalism (reason) and empirical science (nature). In many respects the complex movement of the Enlight­enment constituted the most significant devel­opment in the intellectual history of German Protestant thought since the Reformation and before the ecumenical reorientation in our century. The rise of historical-critical thought during the later Enlightenment replaced the predominantly metaphysical understanding of [492] reality inherited from antiquity by an essentially historical view of the world. So from the end of the eighteenth century Protestant theology was dominated by the question of history, concen­trating particularly on the relationship between revelation and history and between Christianity and other religions, on the impact of modern science on the Christian faith, and on its role in modern society.

In the twentieth century the disestablishment of the churches after the First World War, the breakdown of Protestant identification with the culture of bourgeois Germany, and the redis­covery of eschatological orientation (dialectical theology) and the Reformation heritage (Luther renaissance) led to a new concentration on the problems of faith and God, law and gospel, church and state, Christology and justification. The church struggle in the Nazi period, Barmen, and the ambivalent experience of the confessional church furthered the ecumenical orientation of German Protestant theology and paved the way towards greater unity among the Protestant churches. Thus the Leuenberg Concord between the Lutheran, Reformed and United churches in 1973 in fact ended the centuries-old doctrinal divisions that had characterized German Protestantism since the Reformation. And the last decade of the century saw a growing unity among Protestants in Europe, including not only the great national Protestant churches but also Baptist and Methodist free churches and the heirs to the more radical Reformation movements such as Hussite, Waldensian and Mennonite churches. After the Second World War the experience of the 'death of the God of theistic metaphysics' resulted in a renewed interest in biblical tradition, exegetical (demythologizing) and hermeneutical questions. This led to a renais­sance of Trinitarian thought in academic theology and to a self-conscious engagement with present-day religious, social and political issues in the ecumenical and practice-oriented theological reflections of church bodies and synods. In particular the unsolved problems in the relationship between Christianity and Judaism, the ecumenical relations with Roman Catholicism after the Second Vatican Council, the active but controversial participation in the ecumenical process of the World Council of Churches, the issues of theological feminism, and the need for the Christian churches to define their role in an increasingly multinational and pluri-religious culture in German society were central to Protestant thought in the latter part of the century.

Different needs and problems have thus occasioned German Protestantism to develop, through adaptation and resistance, a variety of theologies through the centuries, always trying to recover and redetermine what it took to be essential in new situations and changing contexts. But for all this diversity, there is also a remarkable continuity, due mainly to two factors: the continuing existence of the territo­rial churches of the Reformation, and the continual reflection of academic theology on the peculiar character of Protestant theology in contrast to Roman Catholicism, required by the historical fact that theological faculties at German universities must by law be either Protestant or Roman Catholic. Through the years this has led to a series of self-referential meta-reflections on the 'essence' of Protestant­ism which are characteristic of German Protestant theology since the Enlightenment.

The common core of Protestant theology

The common core of Protestant theology before 1700 consisted in the rejection of papal authority and the authoritarian clericalism of Roman Catholicism, as well as of the more radical spiritualist, Anabaptist and unitarian movements, and in the insistence that God's grace is mediated only through his Word in law and gospel so that the Bible is the ultimately binding Word of God and the individual consciousness enlightened by the Spirit is the ultimate arbiter in matters of religion and salvation. Accordingly theological reflection concentrated on four major issues: the under­standing of salvific grace as worked out in the doctrine of justification by faith alone (sola fide); the mediation of grace through Christ and the Spirit in word and sacrament (solus Christus, solo verbo); the Bible as the only source of the church's proclamation of justifying faith in Christ and as the ultimate norm of all Christian teaching, creeds, confessions and forms of polity (sola scriptura); and the question of authority in the church as answered by the doctrine of the priesthood of all believers, that is, the conviction that all believers are priests who can intercede [493] for one another, not only the ordained clergy, and that nobody can be forced against conscience, Scripture and reason in matters of faith for the sake of authority.

It was this latter aspect which became prominent when, in the wake of the Enlight­enment, Protestant thinkers sought to determine the 'essence' or 'principle(s)' of Protestantism more explicitly. The sixteenth and seventeenth centuries saw numerous attempts to mediate between the religious parties by stating what is common, central and essential to all Christian life and faith. According to Martin Bucer, for example, the 'substance of the Christian faith' (substantia Christianismi) is not any doctrine or article of faith but the wholehearted and total trust in God and Christ. In the orthodox period and early Enlightenment a number of thinkers (A. Hunnius, G. Calixt, C. Crusius, G.W. Leibniz) tried to overcome the confessional divisions by distinguishing fundamental articles of faith which are shared by all Christians from non-fundamental ones on which believers may differ without loss of salvation. This concentra­tion on what is central and necessary to the Christian faith was generalized by the quest of the 'essence of Christianity' in the Enlight­enment. Some (especially deists) answered it by identifying it with the permanent truths of natural theology. Others, more aware of the problem of history, used the dialectics of internal essence and external form to relativize all actual forms of Christianity to be only historical manifestations (appearances) of an underlying principle (essence). While this was never fully realized by any of its contingent historical manifestations, it was only accessible through the whole historical process of its realizations (see H. Wagenhammer, Das Wesen des Christentums of 1973).

The same dialectics of form and content, appearance and essence, fact and principle were applied to Protestantism in numerous attempts from the mid-eighteenth century to determine its 'essence' or 'principle(s)'. They can be grouped into four characteristic approaches. The first understands Protestantism as the religious manifestation of a non-religious (or not merely religious) principle which is not, and need not be, realized only in religious forms of life. The second sees Protestantism governed by a principle which necessarily leads to specific forms of religious life. The third denies that Protestantism is historically and theologically coherent enough to be explained by one underlying principle at all. And the fourth seeks to combine these approaches by identify­ing the principle of Protestantism as the critical standard by which all religious and non-religious historical forms of Protestantism should be judged. These four approaches are now described in more detail.

First approach Immanuel Kant described the inexplicable fact of freedom as the transcenden­tal principle of autonomous moral self-determi­nation and of all truly human life and was, for this reason, called the 'philosopher of Protes­tantism' by F. Paulsen (1899) and others; but it was above all G.W.F. Hegel who worked out this idea in philosophical detail. For him the willingness 'to accept nothing among one's convictions that has not been justified by thought' is the 'peculiar principle of Protestant­ism' (Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, 1821). It grounds the freedom of the individual in both its private and public dimensions. For freedom is the ultimate ground not only of private morality, uncoerced by external author­ities of whatever sort and guided only by the insights of reason and consciousness, but also of public law and political institutions, the objective historical 'realm of realized freedom'. The Protestant principle of the Reformation ('Here I stand!') is the 'principle of the independent and in itself infinite personality of the individual, of subjective freedom'. As such it is of more than mere local or passing historical significance. It marks the beginning of the full religious, social and political realization of freedom and autonomy in the modern state which has transformed the world.

In the nineteenth century this understanding of the Protestant principle of freedom as the beginning of modernity and the foundation of the modern state inspired both the more liberal Protestant ethos of R. Rothe and the national conservatism of F.J. Stahl. Both contributed in their different ways to the formation of the culture-Protestantism which dominated Ger­many in the latter part of the nineteenth century. For if Protestantism is grounded on the principle of subjective freedom which is most adequately realized in the modern state, then the distinction between church and state is [494] bound progressively to disappear. With the Reformation, Christianity has moved into its secular phase in which the point of the Christian religion is realized not only for the few in the church but for all in the constitutional state.

The same conviction of the progressive realization of the Protestant principle of subjective freedom also guided F.C. Baur in his work on the history of dogma. For him the Reformation was the decisive turning point in the history of Christianity. The Protestant critique of Roman Catholicism was fundamen­tally the protest of autonomous subjectivity against the heteronomous authority of the church. This autonomy was not realized once and for all by the Reformation but is 'a principle capable of infinite development' (Lehrbuch der christlichen Dogmengeschichte, 1867). It is also to be upheld vis-à-vis the Bible, which Protestants treat critically just because they accept it as authority. And it cannot fully be understood without taking the whole, and still developing, history of Protestantism into account. It follows that if we want to understand any Christian doctrine we must trace its historical develop­ment, and it comes as no surprise that most of the major Protestant theologians in the nine­teenth century have at the same time been historians or actively engaged in historical research.

Second approach Baur was not simply applying Hegelian ideas to the study of doctrine. As a young man he was deeply impressed by F.D.E. Schleiermacher's The Christian Faith of 1821-2, which he rightly regarded as inaugurating a new post-Enlightenment phase in Protestant theol­ogy. With this book Schleiermacher sought to justify the union between Lutheran and Reformed churches in Prussia after 1817 by describing their doctrinal positions as two equally valid forms of Protestantism, and Protestantism and Catholicism as two equally legitimate forms of Christianity. The latter difference is, as he succinctly stated in §24 of his Christian Faith, that 'the former makes the individual's relation to the Church dependent on his relation to Christ, while the latter contrariwise makes the individual's relation to Christ dependent on his relation to the Church.' This identified, in an admirably clear way, ecclesiology and the role of the church in the Christian life of faith as the central point at issue between Protestantism and Roman Catholicism; and this has been borne out by the theological and dogmatic developments in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.

Schleiermacher's insight was not immediately grasped by his contemporaries. A. Twesten, his pupil and successor in Berlin, coined the phrase, the 'two principles of Protestantism', that is, the 'formal principle' of Scripture and the 'material principle' of justification by faith alone. And it became a widely held conviction, influentially stated by A. Ritschl, that only the two principles together defined the distinctive character of Protestantism. A special status is assigned to the Bible in Protestant life and thought as the normative witness to God's revelation. But the seventeenth-century theories of the infallible and inerrant inspiration of the biblical texts in all details of content or even verbal expression were widely dismissed as making an idol of the Bible. The biblical texts are historical docu­ments and must be treated according to the general principles of historical criticism and interpretation; the biblical canon is not closed but theoretically open; and although the Bible has ultimate authority in all matters of faith and salvation, theology is not slavishly tied to it but is required to exercise the freedom of critical judgement and reflective reason in interpreting the biblical texts, as much as with any other text. Some, like R. Hagenbach, have therefore concluded that 'the principle of free enquiry' is 'the true principle of Protestantism'; and even in our century it was held by G. Ebeling (1950) that the historical-critical method bears a special affinity to the Protestant spirit.
This was also the conviction of A. Harnack at the turn of the century. In his widely read The Essence of Christianity of 1900 he analyses the differences between Protestantism and Catholi­cism in terms of reformation or 'critical reduction' and revolution or evangelical criti­cism of church dogma and canon law. Protestantism reduced the essence of Christian­ity to the Word of God and the inner experience of faith which corresponds to it. And it objected in principle to all attempts to place the church, its dogma or its laws above the gospel. It is the historical task of Protestantism to safeguard this freedom of true evangelical Christianity against all attempts at religious and moral heteronomy. [495]

Third approach The Schleiermacher—Ritschl—Harnack tradition of understanding Protestant­ism in terms of a (never fully realized) principle or set of principles by which it is clearly marked off from Roman Catholicism came to an end with E. Troeltsch ([1906] 1966). He took Protestantism seriously as a complex historical phenomenon, too diverse to be understood as the successive historical manifestation of one and the same underlying principle, and properly accessible only in terms of the canons of historical-critical method. In his profound historical analysis of Protestantism he identi­fied not the Reformation, but the Enlight­enment as the decisive turning point in the intellectual history of the West. The Reforma­tion and its aftermath still belonged to the religious culture of the middle ages without any direct impact on the modern world. Protestant­ism, accordingly, is not explicable as a single and coherent historical phenomenon. Rather we must distinguish between, on the one hand, the premodern 'old Protestantism' of the orthodox period in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries which continued the uniform religious culture of the middle ages, accepted supernatural revelation and the dogmatic method in theology, and marked itself off against humanism, spiritualism and the more radical Baptist movements, and, on the other, the post-Enlightenment 'neo-Protestantism' which embraces the liberal ideas of freedom, autonomous subjectivity, religious and political tolerance, free scientific enquiry and historical method with its principles of criticism, analogy and correlation. In neither sense, however – and here Troeltsch most clearly departs from Hegelian accounts – can Protestantism be seen as a source of the modern world: old Protestantism is still medieval and premodern, while neo-Protestantism is already part of modernity.
It is here that M. Weber's sociological account of Protestantism ([1904-5] 1930) differs from Troeltsch's historical analysis, which otherwise he parallels in many ways. He focuses on the causal connection between Protestant, especially Calvinist, ethics and the rise of capitalism, and he diagnoses the impact of this 'ascetic Protestantism' on western society as a process of 'disenchantment' which prepared and reinforced the means-end rationality that characterizes the modern sociocultural system of the west.

Fourth approach Troeltsch's and Harnack's versions of liberal Protestantism and their close involvement with the bourgeois culture of Germany were sharply criticized by K. Barth and the other proponents of dialectical theology after the First World War. For them 'Protes­tantism' was a term theologically compromised by neo-Protestantism. They preferred to call their own position 'evangelical', not only because this was closer to the original Reforma­tion usage but because – as especially Barth made clear in both his Christian Dogmatics and Church Dogmatics – their theology was meant to explicate not the self-understanding of a particular (Protestant) church, tradition or religious party, but the Word of God by which all forms of Christianity, including Protestant ones, must be judged. P. Tillich agreed with this but formulated his programme precisely in terms of the Protestant principle to which he gave a new and important twist. He distin­guished between the historically contingent formations (Gestalten) of Protestantism and the universally valid principle of Protestantism which he found expressed in the Reformation doctrine of justification by grace alone (Tillich, 1950). This principle is the permanent protest against, and criticism of, our human temptations to confound the conditional and the uncondi­tional, to elevate finite religious or profane powers to the status of infinite or absolute power. All historical forms of Protestantism are necessarily conditioned and concrete forms of life. They are true only if, as finite and specific formations (Gestalten) of grace, they include both a specific form and the protest against this form, a concrete historical realization and its negation. This intrinsic dialectics safeguards Protestantism in its assigning of absolute value or permanent validity to any doctrines, forms of life or institutions, and it explains its inner dynamics to be semper reformanda, always on the move to better and more adequate Gestaltungen in our profane reality.

Protestant thought and theology

Protestant thought and theology has been pluralist from the beginning. Its sense of identity was not based on the unchanging character of church doctrine or the continuity [496] of ecclesial institutions and traditions but on the permanent proclamation of God's Word as law and gospel, that is, the justification of the sinner by faith alone as testified by Scripture. Scripture, not church doctrine, was accepted as the fundamental norm and source of Christian life and theological reflection, and the confessions and catechisms of the sixteenth century as adequate restatements of the central tenets of biblical teaching in those historical circumstances. Whereas the Lutheran churches subscribed to the Augsburg Confession (1530) as their authoritative confession, the Reformed tradition always knew a variety of confessions and catechisms. After many failures, attempts to overcome the Protestant divide only succeeded in this century in the wake of the Barmen Declaration (1934) with the Leuenberg Concord (1973), which proved to be of more than merely passing or regional importance. The Leuenberg Concord especially has established itself as a paradigm of Protestant ecumenical theology that overcomes old divisions without swerving from the fundamental Protestant tenets of solus Christus, sola scriptura, sola gratia, and sola fide.

Scripture The assertion of the Bible as the norma normans of all Christian life and thought has led Protestant theology since M. Chemnitz, M. Flacius, J. Gerhard and A. Hunnius to develop and defend a doctrine of the authority of the Bible. While Luther insisted on the viva vox evangelii as the Word of God, theologians in the orthodox period identified the (written) Word of God with the canon of the Old and New Testaments which they claimed to be not only inspired but inerrant and infallible. Some even went so far as to hold theories of dictation which made not only the content but the wording of the biblical texts part of God's revelation. On the other hand, the canon never became officially closed in Protestantism, and this openness of the canon served as a constant reminder that the Bible is not to be turned into an icon or idol. It is the authoritative witness to the grace of God in Jesus Christ. Hence the biblical texts were to be made available to every individual. But this verbum externum cannot be understood as the Word of God without the working of the Spirit in the heart of the reader or listener. Hence the orthodox doctrine of the inspiration of Scripture requires the parallel doctrine of the inner testimony of the Holy Spirit: only together do they justify the conviction that the biblical texts are the normative Word of God. Although this was clear in theory, orthodox theologians in practice used biblical texts as inspired premises for dogmatic conclusions or claimed, as pietism did, a specific hermeneutica sacra for them.

For this reason, the rise of historical criticism in the Enlightenment constituted a major challenge to both Protestant orthodox and pietist theologies. While pietist theologians reacted to this by postulating a theologia regenitorum open only to those who are reborn, academic theology distinguished between his­tory and dogma, biblical exegesis and dogmatic and moral doctrine and, since the beginning of the nineteenth century, widely accepted the post-Enlightenment views of biblical criticism. Biblical texts have to be treated as any other ancient literary text. This inspired a formidable and exemplary study of the biblical texts, their ancient settings and historical and literary developments in German Protestant theology during the past two hundred years. But it also produced a growing divide between academic theology and the life of the church. For by concentrating on the biblical texts as such it tended to overlook the fact that these texts must be placed in the context of the life of faith, the proclamation of the church and the working of the Spirit in order to become accessible as the Word of God. So in a sense the history of the Protestant study of the Bible since the Reformation can be described as a series of attempts to determine the proper context in which these texts have to be studied. While the Reformers insisted that not Scripture but the use of Scripture to provoke faith in Christ (usus scripturae) is what theology has to study if it wants to understand the Word of God as law and gospel, orthodox theologians theoretically restated, and thereby changed, this by claiming the perspective of law and gospel to be the decisive dogmatic framework for studying the biblical texts. Instead of concentrating on the faith-provoking use of Scripture, they dog­matically placed the biblical texts in a doctrinal context. This was too theoretical for pietism, and not theoretical enough for the Enlight­enment. Thus whereas pietists claimed not doctrine but the life of the believer to be the proper context for studying the biblical texts, [497] the Enlightenment insisted on the context of reason and experience as the only adequate way to make sense of them.

The study of the Bible has since become torn between the ills of private subjectivity and the dangers of objectifying generalizations or historical descriptions devoid of individual commitment. In the nineteenth century his­tory, other religions, the natural sciences and modern culture became the predominant contexts in which biblical texts were placed, studied and interpreted. The outcome was an immensely increased knowledge of the historical development, cultural immersion, literary re­finement and religious richness of the biblical texts, but at the same time a growing awareness of their at best relative difference from other religious texts, traditions and experiences. Instead of demonstrating its uniqueness, the comparative and historical approaches to the Bible proved its cultural dependence and religious relativity. This made it increasingly difficult for theology to use it as the author­itative norm and source of Christian faith. In the light of the rediscovery of the eschatological nature of the Christian faith by J. Weiss, F. Overbeck and C. and J.C. Blumhardt, theolo­gians like R. Bultmann reacted to the theological breakdown of these historifying and relativizing approaches after A. Schweitzer and Troeltsch by insisting on the existential structures of human life as the key to a proper understanding of the biblical texts and the universal validity of their kerygmatic message. And from the middle of the twentieth century methods of literary criticism and critical hermeneutics became increasingly used to correct the shortcomings of a merely historical-critical, sociological or psychological study of Scripture.

However, none of these methods helped to recover the theological import of Scripture. For the decisive question is not the method but the object of biblical study: as long as theologians study merely the texts rather than the faith-provoking use of these texts, their study of the Bible is ultimately a-theological. Biblical ex­egesis which concentrates on the biblical texts in their various historical/sociological/psychologi­cal contexts is a merely historical/sociological/ psychological discipline. Dogmatic theology must move beyond this by considering the faith-provoking use of these texts in the life of the church if it is to arrive at theological conclusions for today.

Theological method The distinction between historical and dogmatic theology is itself a result of Protestant self-reflection on theologi­cal method. Since the seventeenth century it has distinguished different branches and disciplines of theology no longer in terms of their subject matter (biblical, moral and dogmatic theology) but in terms of the methods used for studying them (theologia positiva, theologia scholastica). In 1787 J.P. Gabler defined biblical theology as a historical discipline distinct from dogmatics, whose task is to restate the Christian faith in a way 'adequate to our time'. Theology's external relationships with other disciplines are thus mirrored in the internal differentiation of theological disciplines according to the tasks pursued and methods used.

This found classical expression in Schleiermacher's Brief Outline of the Study of Theology of 1811, which defined the basic pattern of the study of Protestant theology in Germany for the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. For him theology is a positive, that is, non-speculative or non-foundationalist, science. Just as in the case of medicine and law, both its place in the university and its internal organization are determined by its practical task, the furthering of Christian life in modern society. This leads to its differentiation into three major disciplines. As philosophical theology it relates to the realm of knowledge and science, as practical theology to the realm of life in general and Christian life in particular, but in its central part which comprises both exegetical and dogmatic theol­ogy it is fundamentally a historical discipline. This balanced conception and practical ground­ing of theology avoided both the speculative foundationalism of the idealist tradition and the reduction of theology to a merely historical and comparative study of religion(s), which has endangered the existence of independent theological faculties at German universities from J.G. Fichte, Paul de Lagarde and Overbeck to the present day.

Barth accepted this practical and church-related orientation of theology but criticized Schleiermacher for placing human religion and [498] piety rather than the authoritative Word of God at its centre. And W. Pannenberg tried to move beyond both Barth and Schleiermacher in his Theology and the Philosophy of Science of 1973 by returning to the traditional definition of theology as the science of God. The differ­entiated unity of theology is to be understood not in terms of method but in terms of the unity of its subject matter: God, the all-determining reality. This reality cannot be directly experi­enced in the world but becomes only indirectly accessible in the subjective anticipations of the totality of meaning which is presupposed in all particular experiences. This turns theology into a systematic super-science that seeks to detect the indirect co-givenness of God in all areas of human experience and science. And since the experience of reality as a whole finds symbolic expression primarily in the historic religions, a theory of the history of religions is fundamental for theology. Thus whereas Schleiermacher outlined theology as a fundamentally practical enterprise based on the reality of organized religion or church life, and Barth conceived it as a fundamentally critical enterprise based on God's revelation in Jesus Christ, Pannenberg returned to a pre-modern understanding of theology as a theoretical super-science of the totality of reality.

Doctrine of God Developments in theological method have manifest implications for the doctrine of god. Protestant theology has always insisted on a close relationship between cognitio dei and cognitio hominis, God and faith, theology and anthropology, and it largely followed Luther, who defined the proper subject matter of theology as homo reus et perditus et deus iustificans vel salvator. But this soteriological emphasis in the doctrine of God was worked out in different ways in the history of Protestant theology.

1 The first Lutheran dogmatics, Philipp Melanchthon's Loci communes of 1520, did not contain a separate tract De Deo but insisted that to know Christ, and hence God, is to know his benefits towards us. Thus the very Melanchthon who inaugurated the reception of Aris­totelian metaphysics into Protestant theology provided the decisive argument for neo-Protestant criticism of all metaphysical theol­ogy. In the aftermath of Kant the pro nobis was taken not merely in a soteriological but in an epistemological sense. We cannot know whit God is in himself, as W. Herrmann put it, but only what he does in and for us. By fundamentally distinguishing between objecti­fied and existential reality, Bultmann inter­preted this to mean that the essential relatedness of God and human being does not allow theology to talk about either God or human existence in objectifying terms. Instead we have to interpret all statements about God as statements about human existence in both a soteriological and epistemological sense. This concurred with Schleiermacher's attempt to move beyond the objectifying talk of God in religion, theology and philosophy by showing that all objectifications of God are contingent determinations of our God-consciousness and as such are manifestations of an underlying indeterminate structure of God-consciousness which is the pre-reflective capacity, common to all rational beings, for awareness of an existential relation to that to which we owe our existence, whereas it owes its existence neither to us nor to anything else. Hence 'God' does not name a (supernatural) being but 'the Whence of the feeling of utter dependence'. Accordingly 'all attributes that we ascribe to God are not to be taken as denoting something special in God, but only something special in the way in which the feeling of utter dependence is related to him' (The Christian Faith, §50).

2 The Protestant emphasis on the non-objectification of God is an attempt to safeguard the fundamental difference between God and created being in the tradition of Exodus 20: 4 without completely denying the knowability of God. Hegel, who took the principle of subjectivity to be the principle of Protestant­ism, identified Kant's and Fichte's transcen­dental philosophies as explications of this principle. Kant's critique of Enlightenment theism and its proofs of the existence of God can be seen as a philosophical reworking of the Protestant insistence on a close correlation of God and faith, in that he combines a denial of all theoretical knowledge of God with the postulate of his existence based on the requirements of practical reason. Protestant theology of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries would be unthinkable without his 'I had to abolish knowledge to make room for faith' (Critique of Pure Reason). Fichte went even further by [499] applying this principle to the notion of God itself, that is, to the application of any concepts, in particular the concept of person or person­ality, to God. For him, whatever is concep­tualized cannot be God. It is against this background that Protestant theology, while clinging to the soteriological emphasis of the doctrine of God, developed an increasingly critical attitude towards all sorts of metaphysical theism. Elaborating Blaise Pascal's distinction between the God of the philosophers and the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob, it took an explicitly anti-metaphysical and anti-theistic turn, which characterizes such different posi­tions as Schleiermacher's criticism of natural theology, Ritschl's rejection of all metaphysics in theology, Harnack's view of the corruption of the original gospel by Hellenist thought, K. Barth's and D. Bonhoeffer's critique of the traditional understanding of divine omnipo­tence, impassibility and transcendence, J. Moltmann's and E. Jüngel's insistence on a Trinitarian anti-theism and D. Soelle's para­doxical postulate of atheist belief in God.

3 But it was L. Feuerbach who in his Essence of Christianity of 1841 took this anti-theistic attitude to its atheistic extreme. Claim­ing to explicate Luther's soteriological correla­tion of God and faith he held that 'consciousness of God is man's self-conscious­ness; knowledge of God is man's self-knowl­edge'. For him God is the self-objectification and self-externalization of man's self-knowledge as species being. This made theology an epiphenomenon of anthropology, and it forced Protestant theologians from then on explicitly to mark off their own soteriological accounts of God from this anthropological atheism which made religion the creation of human imagina­tion. Four types of approach to coming to grips with Feuerbach have become particularly prominent.

The first is to place the theological project in the context of a (broadly understood) religious or natural account of God. Thus W. Pannenberg claims, against all tendencies to dissolve or eliminate the concept of God in Protestant theology, that we need a general notion of God that fixes minimal conditions for coherent talk of God if we want to make sense of the gospel and come to grips with Feuerbach's verdict on theology. The Protestant distrust of metaphysics must thus be corrected by transcendentalist (T. Rendtorff, E. Herms) or anthropological (Pannenberg) foundations of Christian talk of God, by recourse to 'original revelation' (P. Althaus) or by placing it in the context of an account of the history of religions as the history of the appearance of the unity of God (Pannenberg).
This is set against the second approach, Barth's attempt to interpret the impossibility of objectifying knowledge of God as manifestation of his sovereign freedom to make himself accessible only in and through his self-revela­tion. Starting from the insight that God can only be known through God as revealed in Jesus Christ, Barth embraced Feuerbach's view of anthropology as the mystery of theology and turned it into a verdict on the whole neo-Protestant tradition since Schleiermacher. Theology must start from the (eschatological) fact of God's self-revelation, not from epistemological considerations of its possibility or assumptions about a fundamental structure of utter dependence or religious a priori of human existence. The fact of God's self-revelation as Lord (Church Dogmatics I/1 §8) manifests God's being as the one who loves freely (Church Dogmatics II/1 §28); and this in turn requires a Trinitarian account of God who reveals himself as love by freely identifying with Jesus Christ on the cross. Thus the mystery of God is his humanity, and his divinity his self-humiliation until death for us. But then Feuerbach's thesis has to be put on its head: theological statements are not anthropological statements in disguise, but all anthropological statements have to be understood as being derivative from Christology (Church Dogmatics II/l) and hence in the last resort from the doctrine of the Trinity.

Barth's comprehensive reworking of the doctrine of God in Christological and Trinitar­ian terms reflects insights which were first worked out in Hegel's speculative philosophy. The contents of the Christian or absolute religion can be philosophically reconstructed, justified and appropriated in a dialectical process outlined in the Science of Logic of 1812. And just as the truth of religion is preserved in philosophy, so the truth of the doctrine of the Trinity is preserved and completed in the speculative theory of the internally differentiated Absolute. Theological [500] Hegelianism was very influential in the nine­teenth century (K. Daub, P. Marheineke, R. Rothe). It has recently been rigorously renewed by F. Wagner, who claims that the only consistent way to oppose the charge of Feuerbach is to base theology not on the consciousness, language or facts of religion but on the self-unfolding process of the self-determining self-determination that is the Absolute.

A fourth attempt takes a vigorously Trinitar­ian approach. Thus E. Jüngel opposes both traditional theism and atheism with a Trinitar­ian account of the God who has revealed himself through the cross of Christ as redeeming love. God is the mystery of the world, but we are unable to discern that mystery unless we place our experience of the world in the light of God's self-revelation in Christ, that is, re-experience all our experience in faith. Thus faith is not the projection of ideal humanity into the idea of God but a second-order experience of the world in which we discern it as (fallen) creation in the light of the love of God disclosed in Christ. God has appropriated death on the cross of Christ, and we cannot adequately talk of God unless we take this into account. Hence in so far as atheism is the negation of theism, it critically belongs to every truly Trinitarian account of God.

The four reactions to Feuerbach all concur in that they rediscover and restate the doctrine of God in Trinitarian terms. After the prevailing theism of the nineteenth century this is one of the most distinctive developments of German Protestant theology in the (second half of the) twentieth century.
The Trinity The Protestant renewal of Trini­tarian theology in the twentieth century starts with Barth, who reacted to the widespread neglect of the doctrine of the Trinity in western theology in his time. Few denied that it was one of the principal mysteries of faith. But it was of little practical significance to the life of faith. Since Augustine and scholastic Augustinianism, Trinitarian thought had come to wear an abstract air, and the western inclination towards a unitarian formulation of the doctrine of God was even further increased by the Enlightenment. Where the doctrine of the Trinity was not held on merely traditionalist grounds, it was discarded altogether or it took on a speculative life of its own.
According to K. Rahner, the first decisive move in the isolation and subsequent steriliza­tion of the doctrine of the Trinity was the separation of the discussion of 'the one God' from the discussion of 'the triune God'. The doctrine of the Trinity became a doctrine alongside others rather than the frame of reference or the grammar of all the others. The Reformation did not achieve a restoration of Trinitarian thought; and at the beginning of the nineteenth century Schleiermacher rightly observed that to achieve this was still one of the unfulfilled tasks of Protestant theology. It remained so for another century. Since the Enlightenment, discussions of the Trinity have become subordinated to a preoccupation with the unitary being of God. Philosophical theism — the belief in the existence of a supreme and beneficent Being - was widely taken over by Christian theologians. Nine­teenth-century attempts to defend Trinitarian thought against these developments led to its absorption into the discussion of the being of God as Absolute, where it took on a speculative life of its own. But this estranged it even further from the life of the church. It left the figurative language of faith without adequate conceptual form. And it opened up a gap between the life of faith and the intellectual engagement with the problem of God.

Philosophers were first to react against these developments. With Feuerbach, K. Marx, S. Freud and F. Nietzsche the speculative move­ment and its attempted rescue of Trinitarian thought came under vigorous attack. Yet since its close association with the Christian tradition had made its vulnerability the vulnerability of Christian theology as well, the criticism of these thinkers was largely unacceptable to (liberal) theology. Only when, in the twentieth century, theology gradually began to divorce itself from Enlightenment theism and its aftermath, could it come to grips with both the speculative tradition and its critics by taking a vigorously Trinitarian and explicitly anti-theistic approach.

Anti-theism, that is, the rejection of Enlight­enment theism, its consequences and its antithesis (atheism), has thus been one of the major motives for Trinitarian theology today. It is the common denominator of such different theologies as those of Moltmann, Jüngel, Pannenberg and Wagner. They all agree that [501] Christian theology, in order to move beyond the barren alternatives of theism and atheism, must be Trinitarian in character. But they differ widely and even irreconcilably in the ways in which they ground their Trinitarian positions.

For E. Jüngel, as for Barth in his later years, the doctrine of the Trinity is Christologically grounded (Jüngel, Entsprechungen: Gott-Wahrheit-Mensch). Originally Barth's doctrine of the Trinity was 'bound up with the concept of revelation, in the strict sense of God's self-revelation which is grounded in God's Trinitar­ian self-unfolding' (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology, 1967-71). This invited the criticism that Barth's doctrine, by working out the structure and implication of the Deus dixit, 'is fashioned out of the logic of God as absolute subject' (J.B. Webster, Eberhard Jüngel, 1986) and that his 'construal of the Trinity as the self-unfolding of a divine subject inevitably does damage to the co-eternity of the divine persons, diminishing their plurality to mere modes of being subordinate to the divine subject' (Pannenberg). But as the Church Dogmatics evolved, the emphasis shifted away from the inner structure of revelation towards the history of Jesus and, in particular, the cross. And in stressing the 'displacement' between Father and Son on the cross, Barth increasingly intensified the divine plurality.

Jüngel criticizes Barth for not taking that process far enough. His own work on the Trinity starts from God's self-identification with the crucified on the cross, and he conceives its function in working out the identity of God's being-for-himself and his being-for-us in the person of Jesus Christ. If God has identified himself with the crucified one, we must 'distinguish God from God' Jüngel, Unterwegs zur Sache, 1972). But the unsurpassable contrast between Father and Son on the cross is not a 'contradiction within God' (Jüngel, God as the Mystery of the World, 1977). God – as Spirit – remains at the same time related to himself in this contrast. This is why we must give not merely a binitarian, but a Trinitarian account of God. Jüngel follows a long tradition of western thought when he describes the Spirit as the reassertion of unity after difference. But he has difficulty in articulating, with any clarity, the personal agency of the Spirit. So instead of pressing from the event of the cross towards an account of the Trinity as an irreducible plural society, he turns to working out the unity of the self-differentiated God in terms of the concept of love: because God is love, he is essentially related, both in himself and in the sense of being open to what is different from him. In God 'to be' and 'to be related' are one and the same; and the character of the ontological relationality of God is love, that is, in Jüngel's definition, 'the unity of life [self-relation] and death [self-loss] in favour of life'. Hence even in his self-abasement on the cross, God is not foreign to himself but eminently true to himself: 'in giving himself away, he does not lose but becomes himself (Webster) because, as God, he does not simply act lovingly but ontologically is love. Hence there is no need to posit 'an essence of God behind his loving pro nobis, for his aseity takes form as loving self-renunciation'.

Jüngel uses the concepts of 'love' and 'relation' to retain the coherence and unity of the divine being without sacrificing the sense of 'displacement' which is introduced into the being of God by the cross. J. Moltmann starts from the same Barthian legacy but moves in a different direction. His case for the necessity of Trinitarian discourse is developed from assert­ing God's real relation to human pain and suffering, supremely exemplified by the cross. On the cross, he says, God was abandoned by God. He not merely holds, as Jüngel does, that the cross occasions the distinction between God and God, but understands the separation of Father from Son in the dereliction of the cross in a full mythological sense. He is able to do this because for him the divine self-separation on the cross is grounded in the priority of persons over relations and the repudiation of any reduction of the three persons to the absolute subject as substance. For him, the primordial reality is the plurality of the persons, and 'the unity of God is only actual in that plurality' (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology). So he develops a pluralist account of a social Trinity of Father, Son and Spirit linked together only by what he calls the Trinitarian history of God. That is to say, the Trinity itself is seen in terms of God's involvement in historical becoming, and although Moltmann goes so far as to deny a definite taxis between the persons 'in favour of a trinity that can be taken "in any order", he [502] nevertheless relates it to our progressive ordering towards a free, creative, relationship of "friendship" to God in the Holy Spirit' (J. Milbank). However, while this ensures that God is not seen as a closed monad, but as a community of loving interaction open to a reality beyond itself, Moltmann so much stresses the personal agency of Father, Son and Spirit, that it becomes difficult to see how it can still be said to be one and the same God. Moreover, in his account of the separation of Father and Son on the cross he does not succeed in doing justice to the agency of the Spirit vis-à-vis Father and Son. He has attempted to remedy this by developing an account not only of the kenosis of the Son but also of the kenosis of the Spirit. But this in fact increases his difficulty in distinguishing clearly between the agency of the Son and that of the Spirit, and virtually bars him from ascribing to the Spirit not merely the function of demon­strating the openness of the triune community but also of establishing its unity by overcoming the difference between Father and Son.

Moltmann's difficulties with the unity of God are one reason for W. Pannenberg to look for a different solution. He agrees with Jüngel and Moltmann that Barth's earlier attempt to develop the doctrine of the Trinity from the formal notion of revelation as expressed in the statement 'God reveals himself as the Lord' is unsatisfactory. Instead of starting from the formal notion of revelation, we must start from the content of God's revelation in Christ. But for Pannenberg this is not so much the cross and the relationship between Father, Son and Spirit in terms of which the cross can be understood as a salvific and revelatory event. Rather it is the particular relationship of the historical Jesus to God and, in particular, the fact that Jesus distinguished himself clearly from the God he called Father and, in renouncing himself completely, made room for the action of the Father and the coming of his kingdom. If this is interpreted, as Pannenberg interprets it, as the self-revelation of God, the way in which Jesus distinguishes himself from the Father discloses that there is an eternal relationship of Father and Son in God. Jesus' self-distinction from God manifests the eternal self-differentiation of the Son from the Father, which corresponds to the self-differentiation of the Father from the Son; and this, for Pannenberg, is the key for a correct interpreta­tion of the cross of Christ (Pannenberg, Systematic Theology, 1988).

However, even if we accept this move from the historical fact of Jesus' obedient attitude to the God he called Father to the eternal mutuality of self-differentiation between Father and Son, we are still left with a binitarian rather than Trinitarian account of God. Only when we move from the cross to the resurrection do we get an adequate under­standing of the third person, for the resurrec­tion, not the cross, 'depicts the dependence of the Father and the Son on the Spirit as the medium of their community' (Schwöbel, 1990, p. 276). Accordingly Pannenberg describes the three persons as three mutually dependent centres of activity and not as three modes of being in one subject.

This conception of the Trinity has a number of important consequences: it dissolves the traditional western distinction between imma­nent and economic relations in so far as 'the mutual self-differentiation of Father, Son and Spirit in the divine economy must be seen as the concrete form of the immanent Trinitarian relations' (Schwöbel, 1990, p. 275). Moreover, the 'mutuality of their active relationships implies for Pannenberg . . . that the monarchia of the Father has to be understood as the result of the cooperation of all three persons' (p. 276) in the divine economy. 'From this perspective the world as a whole can be seen as the history in which it will be finally demonstrated that the Trinitarian God is the only true God' (ibid.).

However, this claim about the eschatological vindication of the Trinity leaves Pannenberg with a problem which he fails to solve. If the full realization of the monarchia of the Father is the kingdom, and if this is brought about only as the final result of the cooperation of all three persons in history, the divine unity of these three centres of activity is hidden and obscure in the course of history. Pannenberg emphasizes the 'eschatological resolution of the tension between the persons of Father, Son and Spirit in revelation and the hiddenness of the unity of God in the world' (Schwöbel, 1990, p. 277). But 'the question is how the three persons of the Trinity can be understood as presenting one divine essence without reducing them to [503] moments or aspects of the one essential Godhead and without positing the divine essence as a fourth subject lurking behind the persons of Father, Son, and Spirit' (p. 277). It is here that Pannenberg's account fails most conspicuously. He does not succeed in offering a Trinitarian solution to the problem of the unity of God which is more than an eschato­logical postponement. Rather he gets stuck in a dualist cul-de-sac: on the one hand he develops the difference of Father, Son and Spirit from his account of revelation in terms of Jesus' self-distinction from the God he calls Father; on the other hand he grounds the unity of God in a metaphysical concept of God's essence prior to and independent of revelation: the concept of God as Infinite. This concept of God, at which we can arrive independently of revelation, as Pannenberg is at pains to show (in Systematic Theology), is normative and regulates all our thinking and speaking of God, including our accounts of the Trinity. For whatever we want to say about Father, Son and Spirit on the basis of revelation, it must accord with the funda­mental idea of God as the Infinite.

It is here that F. Wagner criticizes Pannen­berg for not going far enough. He hopes to remedy the revelationist leftovers which he detects in Pannenberg by basing his account of the Trinity on a theory of the Absolute in the tradition of Hegel and W. Cramer. For him, a convincing and tenable account of God must start from the idea of the Absolute and not from any particular event or understanding of God in history, tradition or religious consciousness. For unless what we say about God is grounded in a theory of the Absolute, which gives content to the idea of God without recourse to religious consciousness and its varying conceptions of God, we shall not be able to distinguish our account of God from superstitious and irrational belief or escape the charge of Feuerbach. On the other hand, the theory of the Absolute must be such that it allows us to explain or make sense of the actual ways in which religious consciousness conceives God. Wagner hopes to achieve this by describing God as the process of absolute self-determination, that is, as the self-determination which determines itself to determine itself. This presupposes an internal differentiation of God into that which determines itself, that which can be determined by itself and that which is the self-determination of the self-determinable by the self-determinator. And he understands this threefold distinction as a conceptual reworking of the difference between Father, Son and Spirit. Hence he claims to have shown that before we turn to analysing revelation or any other event or fact of religion, we can, in purely rational or conceptual terms, arrive at a theory of the Absolute which is intrinsically Trinitarian in structure and character: the Trinity may be a mystery of faith, but it is rationally transparent to philosophical reason.

It is obvious that some very hard questions must be asked as to Wagner's understanding of reason, rationality, conceptual construction and, in particular, his view of the working of language and the translatability of the figurative language of faith into the conceptuality of a theory of the Absolute. All this invites a number of well-known Wittgensteinian criti­cisms. Nevertheless, the problem that he seeks to tackle is a real one: the doctrine of the Trinity is only an adequate doctrine of God if it is more than a mere expression and manifestation of Christian tribalism. It must be construed to provide an account of God – not of a Christian God (whatever that may be) or of some particular beliefs about Father, Son and Spirit which Christians (but not Jews or Muslims) happen to hold over and above their common belief in God. The God of Christian faith is not a particular Christian God but God as experienced and worshipped by Christians. And a doctrine of the Trinity will be inad­equate if it fails to make this clear.

That anti-theism is a common motive of Protestant Trinitarian theology today was already noted. As its second major character­istic has now emerged its Christological orienta­tion, that is, its focus on the history of Jesus and, in particular, the nature of the involvement of God with the death of Jesus upon the cross. This is even true of Wagner, who seeks to show that what Christians confess about God in the light of the death and resurrection of Jesus Christ is a universal truth about God, accessible not only to faith but also to reason. So present-day Protestant Trinitarianism clearly reflects its traditional soteriological concern and Christ-centred faith.

Christology The question of the significance of Jesus Christ lies at the heart of Protestant [504] theology, and in Christology it has made the most important contributions to Christian theology since the Enlightenment (McGrath, 1986). The Reformers appropriated classical Chalcedonian Christology (see the third chapter of the Augsburg Confession of 1530) but reworked it soteriologically. Theologians in the orthodox period systematically distinguished between the person and the work or office of Jesus Christ in terms of an ontology of nature, person and act. To bring this ontological account of Christ into line with the biblical story, and in particular with Philippians 2: 5ff, the basic text for Lutheran Christology, they developed the doctrine of the two stages of Christ's life, the status exinanitionis and status exaltationis. But with the Enlightenment and the rise of historical consciousness, the problem of history and the question of the relationship between dogma and history became too pressing to be left to such a doctrinal appendix. It permeated the whole Christology and theology of Protestantism and caused its most profound reorientation since the Reformation. It kept its soteriological emphasis, and hence the categorial distinction between person and work of Christ. But it now restated it in terms of the 'historical Jesus' and his 'meaning for us'.

In 1774-8 G.E. Lessing published the Wolfenbüttel Fragments of H.S. Reimarus's Schutzschrift für die vernünftigen Verehrer Gottes which inaugurated over a century's quest of the historical jesus. For the Enlightenment, the ultimate arbiter of knowledge and truth in religion and theology as well as in all other areas was neither Scripture nor tradition, but reason and experience. It thus challenged the meta­physical Christologies of orthodoxy on epistemological, rationalist and moralist grounds. The rationally unacceptable two natures doctrine was replaced by more reasonable moral or aesthetic interpretations of Christ's significance. The doctrine of the uniqueness of the God-Man was restated in terms of Jesus as a morally perfect man, a teacher of truth in his lifetime and a supreme example of self-giving in his death. And the reliability of the biblical accounts of Christ on which the doctrinal claims concerning his unique status were based was questioned with increasing scepticism. Lessing interpreted the contrast between the authority of the 'written tradition' and its 'inner truth' in terms of the difference between 'accidental truths of history' and 'necessary truths of reason'; and he confessed to being personally unable to cross 'the ugly great ditch' between history and reason, between the particularity of historical fact and the generality of rational truth, which did not allow the deduction of the doctrinal accounts of Christ from the biblical accounts of Jesus (Ãœber den Beweis des Geistes und der Kraft, 1777). Likewise, Kant regarded it as impossible for any individual historical being to be the full revelation of eternal truth. Kant believed that the 'ideal of a humanity well pleasing to God' was indeed encapsulated in the idea of a man like Jesus Christ. But the practical belief in such a son of God does not require 'any example from experience' but is based on the requirements of practical reason alone. This ideal or archetype is self-authenticating even if there was never a human being exemplifying it (Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, 1793).

Protestant theology did not follow Kant's proposal, which went beyond the Enlighten­ment accounts of Jesus as moral teacher and example of moral perfection. But throughout the nineteenth century and beyond, it accepted Kant's close correlation of Christology and the idea of the kingdom of God. This is as true of Schleiermacher and Hegel as it is of Ritschl and Barth. Schleiermacher developed his Christol­ogy in The Christian Faith by arguing back from 'the state of the Christian, inasmuch as he is conscious of divine grace' (§§91-112) to its sufficient cause, the redeeming influence of Jesus on the collective life of the Christian community. The collective life of the Christian community owes its existence to the archetypal potency and perfection of Jesus' God-con­sciousness, mediated historically and socially through normal causal channels. He is redeemer in that he, and he alone, is the archetype of the final perfection of God-consciousness, and at the same time the one in which it was historically manifested. As such he exerts an assimilative power capable of bringing about an increasing perfection of God-consciousness in us, by drawing us not by supernatural magic or as moral model of perfect humanity but through the normal channels of communicating the gospel into the Christian community that is dominated by his perfect God-consciousness. [505]

This novel starting point allowed Schleiermacher to reconstruct and appropriate both the orthodox Christological dogma and the Enlight­enment criticism of it. By transcending the supernaturalism of orthodoxy as well as the rationalism and naturalism of the Enlighten­ment, he inaugurated a new area of Christolo­gical thought. This was partly due to his new understanding of nature and history and, in particular, to his (romantic) conception of the individual universal that went beyond the Enlightenment contrast of particularity with generality in distinguishing history and nature. History is the realm of human action and to be studied by ethics; nature and realm of events governed by causal laws and to be studied by physics; religion mediates between the two by combining the individuality of autonomous action with the universality of natural law. A. Ritschl restated this from neo-Kantian premises as the dichotomy between fact and value, and argued that Christological statements are not metaphysical statements of supernatural facts about Christ's nature but value-judgements about his 'value for us'. Jesus' calling (Beruf) was 'the establishment of the universal ethical fellowship of mankind' (The Christian Doctrine of Justification and Reconciliation, 1870-4). Those who believe in him as Christ participate in the kingdom of God as mediated through the community of faith. And they are reconciled to God in that they thereby participate in the same qualitative relationship to God as Jesus, the founder of their religion. Thus Jesus' unique­ness is understood not ontologically or meta­physically but historically: he is the unique founder of the Christian church. This rejection of metaphysics and of the metaphysically interpreted classical Christology was typical of liberal theology towards the end of the nine­teenth century. It was brought to its logical conclusion by A. Harnack, who insisted that dogma was the Hellenistic corruption of the original simple gospel which was rediscovered in the Reformation. The irreducible element of the gospel concerns man's relationship with God the Father and the infinite value of the human soul, whereas 'Jesus does not belong to the gospel as one of its elements, but was the personal realization and power of the gospel, and we still perceive him as such' (The Essence of Christianity). Through the Christian community we are linked to him historically, not theologi­cally, in that to have faith in Jesus Christ is to have faith in God the Father, like Jesus Christ, rather than to believe any dogma about Christ. Christological problems are thus turned either into particular problems of history or universal problems of human personality, and the Christian faith is interpreted historically as a religiously founded culture of humanity and the infinite value of personality.

The conflict between universal validity and historical uniqueness had already governed Hegel's critique of Schleiermacher. For him, the identification of archetypal God-conscious­ness with the historical Jesus is unfounded as long as it is only inferred as sufficient cause from the religious consciousness of grace. Instead we must argue from God to religious consciousness, not the other way round. The incarnation must be the starting point, not the reinterpreted conclusion, of Christological reflection, for the ideal unity of God and man is demonstrated through the appearance of God in history in the person of Jesus Christ. But upon what grounds can we justify the identification of the speculative principle of the incarnation with the historical individual Jesus Christ? This was D.F. Strauss's, and in a sense also S. Kierkegaard's, question addressed to both Hegel's and Schleiermacher's Christologies. But whereas Strauss took the speculative horn of the dilemma, Kierkegaard took the historical one. Thus Strauss argued that the speculative idea of divine-human unity cannot be historically embodied in one specific individual but only in the whole history of the human species — an idea that was effectively taken up by Feuerbach's anthropotheism. For Strauss, the historical Jesus has at best only an accidental connection with the archetypal Christ. Hence the tasks of historical criticism and doctrinal theology must not only be distinguished but must clearly drift apart. Attempts to base a life of Jesus on the Gospel accounts are doomed to failure, as he showed in his The Life of Jesus of 1835-6 in that they are heavily impregnated with mythical expressions of religious imagination, that is, they report not only facts of Jesus' life but, in the form of factual discourse, the way the significance of his life was perceived and experienced by the early Chris­tian community. Doctrinal theology that is [506] concerned with truth cannot start from a reinterpretation of these imaginative myths, but only from the speculative idea of divine-human unity. And this, as he proved by his own monistic pantheism, may be done in a way that has little, if any, connection with the historical figure of Jesus of Nazareth. Kierkegaard, on the other hand, sought to solve the dilemma between historical uniqueness and universal validity by concentrating not on the speculative idea of divine-human unity but on the 'absolute paradox' of becoming contemporary to the incarnate son of God in faith. But by interpreting faith as ahistorical contemporane­ity with Jesus, he, just as Strauss, dissolved the theological significance of the historical Jesus: the life of Jesus, beyond the mere fact of his existence, is without religious significance. Both Strauss and Kierkegaard thus paved the way for R. Bultmann's programme of demythologizing in the twentieth century.

Not only Strauss and Kierkegaard reacted critically to the quest for the historical Jesus that dominated Christology following Schleiermacher's Life of Jesus published posthumously in 1864. In the second half of the century a number of fundamental criticisms emerged from various theological quarters: (1) the kenotic critique of G. Thomasius; (2) the dogmatic critique of M. Kähler; (3) the apocalyptic critique of J. Weiss and A. Schweitzer; and (4) the historical critique of E. Troeltsch.

1 Confessional Lutherans like E. Sartorius, E. König, C. Hofmann and Thomasius who sought to retain traditional Christological orthodoxy in the face of historical criticism and the life of Jesus movement, turned to Philippians 2: 7 and its idea of a self-emptying of the divine in the incarnation as well as to the Lutheran doctrine of the communicatio idiomatum to accommodate incarnational Christology to the full historical humanity of Jesus. Operating within the circle of the two natures doctrine they interpreted the incarnation not as the assumption of humanity but as the self-emptying, or laying aside, of divinity. But if the kenosis is taken to mean a self-limitation of the divine in the sense that the eternal Son actually changed himself into a man and allowed his eternal self-consciousness to be completely extinguished (W.F. Gess), then we are not only faced with the problem of distinguishing the kenosis from the annihilation of the Son of God, but also of accommodating the idea of divine self-limitation to that of divine unchangeability and impassibility. The latter problem Thomasius sought to solve by distin­guishing between immanent and relative attri­butes of God, for example between absolute power and omnipotence, or absolute truth and omniscience. The kenosis is an expression of the divine rather than a denial of it, in that it is the Son's voluntary renunciation of those divine attributes that were incompatible with a genuinely human existence without thereby also divesting himself of those immanent attributes that define his divinity as his free capacity to limit himself. Self-limitation here becomes not only compatible with, but su­premely characteristic of, God's divinity. And although this was sharply criticized by J. Dorner for dissolving the fundamental postulate of divine unchangeability, it was taken up in modified ways in the Trinitarian Christologies of the later Barth, Moltmann and Jüngel.

2 In quite a different way Kähler in The So-Called Historical Jesus and the Historic, Biblical Christ of 1892 criticized the Jesus of the 'Life-of-Jesus' movement as an invention of the modern historical mind which was no better than the dogmatic Christ of traditional Chris­tology that it sought to replace. For him, "the real Christ is the preached Christ' whose saving significance is encapsulated in the New Testa­ment portrait of Christ as saviour. Hence the 'biblical, historical (geschichtliche) Christ', not the 'historical (historische) Jesus' of the pseudo-historical theology of liberal Protestantism is the proper starting point for Christology.

3 Although Kähler was severely criticized by W. Herrmann, O. Ritschl and others for misrepresenting the value of historical-critical method and ignoring the problem of whether the 'historical Christ' of the Bible was not merely a product of faith rather than a fact of history, the general thrust of his criticism was borne out by Schweitzer's Quest of the Historical Jesus of 1906. He saw the whole life-of-Jesus approach as operating within fundamental alternatives, of which he thought we must always accept the first and reject the second: either purely historical or purely supernatural; either synoptic or Johannine; either eschatological or non-eschatological. For him, the [507] rediscovery of the apocalyptic character and strongly eschatological bias of Jesus' proclama­tion of the kingdom of God by J. Weiss had called Ritschl's essentially Kantian interpreta­tion of the kingdom of God as the exercise of the moral life in society into question, and made Jesus a strange figure from an alien first-century apocalyptic milieu without similarity to the Christ of the doctrinal Christology of the church.
4 From a different angle Troeltsch and the history of religions school also radically undermined the foundations of constructive theology by historical research. For Troeltsch, the quest for the historical Jesus was not historical enough. Historical method consis­tently applied according to the principles of criticism, analogy and correlation must study Christianity as any other religion. It also bars any way from historical accounts of Jesus to dogmatic conclusions as an unfounded metabasis. The centrality of Christ within the Christian community is to be explained sociologically and psychologically, not religiously or theologically. Whereas theologians from Schleiermacher to Harnack saw the significance of Jesus in his formative influence on the creation of the Christian community, which still allowed for some sort of doctrinal expression, Troeltsch analysed Christianity in general social terms, without recourse to a specific influence of Jesus beyond the sociopsychological requirements of the Christian community to ground its cult in historical fact.

This radical dissolution of dogmatics into historicism has been strongly counteracted since the First World War. The Either-Or way in which liberal Protestantism posed the Christological problem, as well as the historical and humanist approach by which it sought to solve it, was radically rejected by (1) the dialectical Christologies of K. Barth and E. Brunner; (2) the kerygmatic Christology of Bultmann; (3) the hermeneutical theologies from Fuchs to Ebeling; and (4) the Trinitarian Christologies of Moltmann and Jüngel.

1 For Barth it was the risen Christ rather then the historical Jesus who is central to Christology. Hence its fundamental framework is eschatology, not history and morality. Just as Schleiermacher argued from the historical fact of the Christian consciousness of grace to Jesus' perfect God-consciousness as its sufficient cause within the paradigm of history, so Barth argued from the eschatological reality of the risen Christ to a Trinitarian account of God as its sufficient cause within the paradigm of escha­tology. For him, Christology starts from a specific divine activity, not from historical facts and their (private or cultural) meaning or significance; and its task is to explain this divine activity not in terms of an analogia entis and doctrine of analogical predication but in terms of an analogia fidei, by showing it to be grounded in the free and loving being of the triune God. Thus a Christ-centred eschato­logical realism of divine activity rather than a Jesus-centred historicism or person-centred existentialism is his answer to the Christological developments of the nineteenth century. And this is worked out in detail in the monumental Christology of his Church Dog­matics.

2 While Bultmann agreed that historical research can never lead to any conclusion that can serve as the basis of faith, he differs from Barth in that he interprets the eschaton, not realistically as an act of God in time and history, but existentially as the moment of existential crisis in which we are confronted by the divine kerygma addressed to us. The kerygma is not mere information about God, but conveys insights concerning our human existence. It does not only inform us about authentic existence but occasions a crisis and demands an existential decision on our part. Since the kerygmatic character of the New Testament message is buried under man-made myth, Bultmann propagates the existential demythologization of the New Testament. Its proclamation of the way of life inaugurated by the Christ-event can and must be restated in contemporary existential terms because it is a present possibility for us and may be appropriated as our own. The kerygma goes beyond history in that it compresses the existential significance of the history of Jesus into an eschatological demand. But there is no way to go beyond the eschatological kerygma to more basic historical foundations without dissolving it: the fact of Jesus' existence, not any details of his actual life, is all that is necessary for the kerygma to effect the existential transition from inauthentic to authentic existence. Hence Christology which [508] explicates the kerygma knows Jesus only as the one who is proclaimed as Christ. The quest for the historical Jesus is not only impossible (as the form-critical approach to the Gospels made clear) but theologically unnecessary and illegiti­mate. For the historical Jesus and his message as such have no decisive significance for the Christian faith.

3 Many, like E. Käsemann, G. Bornkamm, E. Fuchs, G. Ebeling or W. Pannenberg, did not agree. For them, it is of vital importance that faith in Christ has its roots in the person and proclamation of Jesus. For the kerygma-based Christology of the church would be an imaginative illusion if it were a misinterpretation of the life and message of the historical Jesus. Thus the new quest of the historical Jesus is not another attempt to reconstruct a life of Jesus from the gospels, but to demonstrate that the kerygma arises with Jesus himself rather than with the primitive Christian community. His life and message were implicitly what his proclama­tion as Christ has made explicit, as Fuchs seeks to demonstrate from the total correspondence between Jesus' life and message, Pannenberg from Jesus' filial relationship to the God he called Father, and Ebeling from the way the event of the cross has become the word of the cross. The relationship between the Jesus of history and the Christ of faith, and hence between history and dogma, is thus focused on the eschatological relationship between cross and resurrection.

4 By restating this in terms of the relation between the death of Jesus and the life of God, J. Moltmann and E. Jüngel have argued that because of God's creative identification with the crucified Jesus as disclosed in the resurrection, the theological problem of the crucified Jesus is the problem of the crucified God, which can only be solved in Trinitarian terms. Explicating the eschatological relation between cross and resurrection, Christology is thus once again emphatically grounded in Trinitarian theology and the Christian doctrine of God in the cross of Christ.

Ecclesiology One of Schleiermacher's important legacies to Protestant theology is that every Christology implies an ecclesiology, and vice versa. Just as they did not want to depart from traditional Christological doctrine, the Refor­mers did not want to found a new church but renew the old one. Yet the political, social and religious situation soon forced them to create state-based territorial churches independent of Rome. These Lutheran, Reformed and (later) united churches were organized according to the principle eius regio, eius religio; existed in a close symbiosis with state and society until 1918; and before the Enlightenment, made it difficult if not impossible for other religious and minority groups to practise their own faith. The controversies between Lutheran and Reformed churches in the orthodox period, the rise of pietist reform movements in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the confessionalist awakening and growing secularism in the nineteenth century, the restructuring of the churches after 1918 and the questioning and partial overcoming of traditional confessional divisions in the ecumenical endeavours of the twentieth century have all left their stamp on German Protestant ecclesiology.

The Protestant revolt against authoritarian clericalism is clearly reflected in the Lutheran and Reformed confessions of the sixteenth century. The church is a creatura verbi divini and church government a matter of all Christians, not just the clergy. For while the public proclamation of the gospel through word and sacrament requires an ordained ministry, those ordained are only functionally, not sacramentally, set apart from other Christians. That is to say, neither the distinction between clergy and laity nor that between ministry and episcopacy are of any deeper theological significance: they only mark differences of tasks and functions within the Christian community that in principle are open to, and the duty of, every Christian.

This devaluation of church hierarchy and the corresponding revaluation of the equal rights and duties of every Christian in the church has had numerous practical and theoretical effects on German Protestant ecclesiology. It is reflected in the fact that church government in Lutheran and Reformed churches was never left to the ordained ministry alone. It inspired the pietist reform movement in forming ecclesiolas in ecclesia (P.J. Spener). And it shows in the Lutheran doctrine of the two regiments of God that explains the relationship between church and society not in institutional terms but by stating the different rights and duties of every [509] Christian to engage in both ecclesial and political activities without confusing or mer­ging them. However, the Protestant view of the church is not monolithic. Even within the Lutheran or Reformed traditions it has allowed for widely differing ecclesiological visions and developments since the Enlightenment. At the one extreme the church is seen to achieve its end only by dissolving into society, thereby transforming it into a culture dominated by the values of humanity, personality and mutual love. Thus by distinguishing between church and religion in the tradition of Kant and Hegel, the church is understood as a means for more general religious ends which, as in particular R. Rothe argued, can only be realized by a transition of Christianity from its church-based form into the secular form of the modern state. This view lies at the bottom of the cultural Protestantism of the nineteenth century and also governs the 'Christianity outside the church' movement of the twentieth century. At the other extreme there is the neo-Lutheran confessionalism of C. Harms, W. Loehe and A.F.C. Vilmar in the nineteenth or W. Elert in the twentieth centuries, which insists in the light of the Augsburg Confession, chapter 7, and the doctrine of the two regiments on the irreducible existence of the church in, and its permanent contrast to, society. However, the church is not a civitas platonica, as Melanchthon had pointed out, since its constitutive activities, the proclamation of the gospel by word and sacrament through which God the Spirit works faith and salvation, are public events in time and history. The church is a complex reality both hidden (not invisible!) in society as God's activity and at the same time visible and part of society as human activity. Orthodox theology concentrated more on the first aspect, neo-Protestant ecclesiology on the second. Since the activities of the church are part of the general fabric of actions and institutions that make up society, as Schleiermacher and Hegel have shown in their different ways, ecclesiology cannot proceed in merely doctrinal terms. Instead any theologically viable account must include external perspectives on the church such as are provided by social philosophy (Schleiermacher), the social sciences (Troeltsch), the philosophy of culture (Tillich), philosophical (Bonhoeffer) and empirical sociology or the sociology of organizations (E. Herms; N. Luhmann).

This need to combine doctrinal and extra-doctrinal considerations in theological accounts of the church is most obvious in the case of church law. At the turn of the century R. Sohm claimed that there exists a fundamental contra­diction between church law and the essence of the church as ecclesia invisibilis, whereas Harnack insisted that the development of church law in the early centuries was both adequate and indispensable for the Christian church as a visible historical institution. The problem posed itself again in the crisis of German Protestantism marked by the Barmen Declaration (1934), which claimed that the church has to pay witness to Jesus Christ not only by its gospel message but also by its institutional order and regulations. Bonhoeffer was one of the first to see this clearly and to take the sociological form of the church as a dogmatic problem (Sanctorum Communio, 1927). His understanding of the church as 'Christ existing as community' and his (later) views of the church as essentially a 'church for others' have deeply influenced Protestant public opinion and ecclesiology after 1945. In the German Democratic Republic they inspired the programme of a 'church in socialism', and in both East and West Germany they contributed considerably to the ecumenical reorientation of Protestant theology in the second half of the twentieth century.

In the twentieth century Protestant theology has moved into its ecumenical phase (see ecumenism). But the problem of the unity of the Christian churches has been part of its history from the beginning. In the Reformation period it showed in the Protestant demand for a general ecumenical council; in the seventeenth century in the attempts to base a union on the 'consensus quinquesaecularis' (G. Calixt) or on 'fundamental articles' acceptable to all Chris­tians; in the eighteenth century in the pietist attempt (A.H. Francke, N. Zinzendorf) to give priority to Christian life and experience over confessional orthodoxy; in the nineteenth century in the external and internal mission and diakonia irrespective of confessional or religious ties; and in the twentieth century in the ecumenical movement, which was started and dominated by Protestant churches for half a [510] century. German Protestant theology actively participated in this process. It achieved remark­able results, such as the Leuenberg Concord (1973) and numerous bilateral and multilateral agreements with other churches and confes­sional traditions. But it also reproduced its differences concerning the task of the church and its relation to society and politics at an international level, and introduced its own divisions between liberal and conservative or evangelical positions on church, mission, political theology and social engagement of the churches into the ecumenical movement. It has influenced the ecumenical movement and was influenced by it, and its future is now indissolubly tied up with the future of the worldwide Christian movement. Within this new context German Protestant theology is still very much alive today; it has a rich legacy to convey to a world that is increasingly pluralist and diversified, secular and ahistorical; and it knows that it can only be true to its past if it faces up to the problems of today and tomorrow.

Bibliography

Barth, K. 1973: Protestant Theology in the Nineteenth Century: Its Background and History. Valley Forge: Judson Press.
Birkner, H.-J. 1971: Protestantismus im Wandel. Aspekte - Deutungen - Aussichten. Munich: Clau­dius.
Bossuet, J.-B. [1688] 1841: Histoire des variations des Eglises protestantes, Oeuvres, vol. 4. Paris: Didot Frères.
Dorner, J.A. 1867: Geschichte der protestantischen Theologie, besonders in Deutschland. Munich: Cotta.
Ebeling, G. 1950: Die Bedeutung der historisch-kririschen Methode für die protestantische Theo­logie und Kirche, Zeitschrift für Theologie und Kirche 47, pp. 1-46.
Frank, G. 1862-1905: Geschichte der protestantischen Theologie, 4 vols. Leipzig: Breitkopf und Hartel.
Frey, C. 1989: Die Ethik des Protestantismus von der Reformation bis zur Gegenwart. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus G. Mohn.
Graf, F.W., ed. 1990: Profile des neuzeitlichen Protestantismus, vol. 1, Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus G. Mohn.
Greschat, M., ed. 1978: Theologen des Protestantismus im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert, 2 vols. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.
Groh, J.E. 1982: Nineteenth Century German Protestantism: The Church as Social Model. Washington DC: University Press of America.
Härle, W., and Herms, E. 1982-3: Deutschsprachige protestantische Dogmatik nach 1945, Verkündigung und Forschung 27, pp. 2-100; 28, pp. 1-91.
Heim, K. 1963: The Nature of Protestantism. Philadelphia: Fortress Press.
Heron, A. 1980: A Century of Protestant Theology. Philadelphia: Westminster Press.
Hirsch, E. [1946] 1968: Geschichte der neueren evangelischen Theologie im Zusammenhang mit den allgemeinen Bewegungen des europäischen Denkens. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus G. Mohn.
Huber, W. 1987: Protestantismus und Protest, im Verhältnis von Ethik und Politik. Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt.
Kähler, M. 1989: Geschichte der protestantischen Dogmatik im 19. Jahrhundert, ed. E. Kähler. Wuppertal/Zurich: Brockhaus.
Lohff, W. 1985: Die Konkordie reformatorischer Kirchen in Europa: Leuenberger Konkordie. Frank­furt am Main: Lembeck.
McGrath, A.E. 1986: The Making of Modern German Christology: From the Enlightenment to Pannenberg. Oxford: Blackwell.
Marty, M.E. 1972: Protestantism. New York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston.
Mildenberger, F. 1981: Geschichte der deutschen evangelischen Theologie im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.
Moltmann, J., ed. 1990: Religion der Freiheit: Protestantismus in der Moderne. Munich: Kaiser.
Müller, H.M. 1991: Kulturprotestantismus: Beiträge zu einer Gestalt des modernen Christentums. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus G. Mohn.
Paulsen, F. 1899: Kant der Philosoph des Protestantis­mus. Berlin: Reuther und Reichard.
Ritschl, O. 1908-27: Dogmengeschichte des Protestantismus, 4 vols. Leipzig: J.C. Hinrichs'sche Buchhandlung; vols 3-4. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.
Rupp, G. 1977: Culture-Protestantism: German Liberal Theology at the Turn of the Twentieth Century. Missoula: Scholars Press.
Schütte, H. 1966: Protestantismus. Sein Selbstverständnis und sein Ursprung gemäss der deutschsprachigen Theologie der Gegenwart und eine kurze katholische Besinnung, Essen-Werden: Fredebeul und Koenen.
Schwöbel, C. 1990: Wolfhart Pannenberg. In The Modern Theologians: An Introduction to Christian Theology in the Twentieth Century, vol. 1, ed, D.F. Ford. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 257-92.
Tillich, P. 1948: The Protestant Era. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tillich, P. 1950: Der Protestantismus: Prinzip und Wirklichkeit. Stuttgart: Steingrüben.
Troeltsch, E. [1906] 1966: Protestantism and Progress: A Historical Study of the Relation of Protestantism to the Modern World, trans. Boston: Beacon Press.
Weber, M. [1904-5] 1930: The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. T. Parsons, ed. R.H. Tawney. London: Allen and Unwin.
Welch, C. 1972-85: Protestant Thought in the Nineteenth Century, 2 vols. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Source: McGrath, The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Modern Christian Thought, pp. 489-511.
Share:

0 comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.

COPE LANGH KHAN KAM

Click List of Topics

Featured Post

URBAN YOUTH LEADERSHIP

By: Cope Langh Khan Kam Youth Urban Leadership One of the possible issues that cause Youth Leadership Instability in the Church m...

Wikipedia

Search results

´